24 Jun 2017

A Letter to Heide Hatry (Parts I and II)

Heide Hatry


I. The Sickness Unto Death

Dear Heide,

Many thanks for your fascinating five-part response to the posts on Torpedo the Ark that referred to your recent body of work, Icons in Ash. I'm touched that you kindly took the time to write not only at length, but with such good grace and critical intelligence. I will attempt to reply in the same manner and to each part in turn. However, I should point out that I'm unconvinced about the possibility (or desirability) of serious discussion: either two people agree - in which case there's not much to say; or they disagree - in which case there's nothing to say. This renders the attempt to exchange ideas narcissistic and futile; a vacuous academic game to be avoided at all costs.

Having said that, there's no need for absolute silence; we can surely keep company and converse without attempting to discuss things and break words apart. It's just a question of bearing in mind this idea of incommensurability and accepting that even speaking subjects who seem to share a language never truly understand one another; that there's always a pathos of distance between things, between people. It's not surprising, therefore, that you fail to "recognise" yourself in my words: for I don't know you. Indeed, if I might be permitted to paraphrase Nietzsche once more, we knowers are unknown even to ourselves ...

You ask if I have "really looked" at your work. Sadly, as I don't live in New York, I've not been afforded the opportunity to do so. I've had to make do with printed reproductions and images online. Perhaps this explains why I haven't "felt" it (though I'm not quite sure I know what you mean by this). Ultimately, it's fair to say that I'm more interested in what you (and others) say about the portraits, rather than the portraits themselves. As I'm neither a practicing visual artist, nor a qualified art critic, you'll have to forgive my insensitivity.   

I'm pretty much in agreement with your remarks on Deleuze and Guattai; certainly theirs was a project critical and clinical in nature and they regarded themselves as cultural physicians. But it should be noted that they have a very unusual understanding of what constitutes health and it doesn't coinicide with the dreary and functional good health which we've been given and which we're endlessly told we have to look after.

In fact, it's an irresistable and delicate form of health that the conventionally robust who eat their five-a-day and visit the gym after work might find feeble and sickly. The key thing is, whilst strength preserves, it's only sickness that advances. That's why we need our decadents, our convalescents, and those artists and philosophers who have returned from the Underworld with bloodshot eyes and pierced eardrums. You mention Artaud and Rimbaud. I might mention others - such as D. H. Lawrence, for example. Theirs may not have been "salutary examples of the good life", but they were vital figures nevertheless. 


II. On Death and Nietzsche's Eternal Recurrence       

I'm very sorry if my suggestion that, in calling up the spirits of deceased loved ones, you were seeking to have the last word upset you. It might well be that such a remark displays all of the faults you ascribe to it (banality, reductiveness, wrong-headedness, tone-deafness, remarkable ungenerosity, and wilful misunderstanding). Nevertheless, it surely has to be admitted that the dead, being dead, have no right of reply and cannot give consent.

In fact, one of the irritating things about the dead is that no matter how loud you cry and scream at them, or or how fully you explain yourself to them, they never listen and they never respond. Again, it's not so much rudeness or indifference on their part - it's just how they are (dead).

Obviously, we disagree on this ... It might please you to know, however, that I like the idea of the souls of the dead investing the lives of the living. And of the dead who do not die, but look on and silently help. It might be noted too that I've written sympathetically and approvingly of necrophilia and spectrophilia. But still - with the possible exception of those posthumous individuals who, as Nietzsche says, only enter into life once they've died - I can't quite accept that the dead have a great deal to offer (although, to be fair, neither do the noisy majority of the living). 

Moving on ... I opened my eyes wide in astonishment when you referred to (human) life as the "most glorious phenomenon" - but decided you were only teasing. I mean, Heide, c'mon - you can't be serious! At best life is epiphenomenal - a rare and unusual way of being dead, as Nietzsche describes it. To privilege life over death is just prejudice. I'm all for living life joyfully, but it's only ever a practice of joy before death and the real festivity begins when we make a return to material actuality.

To be clear: I'm not championing that negative representation of death conceived as a form of judgement which comes at the end of a life upon which, as you say, it "exerts an oppressive and defeatist effect". Rather, I'm speaking of death as a form of becoming (a line of flight and a dissolution). You mention at this point in your comments Nietzsche's concept of eternal recurrence and, clearly, it speaks of both types of death which Keith Ansell-Pearson characterises as heat death and fire death. Please note, however, that there's never any attempt at reconciliation in Nietzsche's work.

I wouldn't say Nietzsche's eternal recurrence is a "life-affirming" teaching (even you put this phrase in scare quotes); what it affirms, rather, is repetition and the difference engendered by it (the Same - das Gleiche - is not a fixed essence and does not refer to a content in and of itself). Nor is it a cheerful teaching - it's a form of tragic pessimism; there's no promise of salvation or any hope of transcending existence precisely as is. The happiness it promises is forever tied to pain and suffering (as well as moonlight, spiders and demons).      


To read parts III-V of this letter to Heide Hatry, please click here

To read Heide Hatry's extensive series of comments please see the posts to which they are attached: Heide Hatry: Icons in Ash and On Faciality and Becoming-Imperceptible with Reference to the Work of Heide Hatry


1 comment:

  1. 1. Rather than engendering some kind of dialogical futility, it's surely more likely that sophisticated minds will both agree and disagree with each other, in which case the scope for nuanced intercourse is almost endless. Philosophical dialogue, moreover, is often about the valuable clarification of the basis for meaningful dis/agreement or, in a Heideggerian spirit, defining and refining the privilege of ontological questioning. (Aristotle saw philosophy as rooted in wonder - which is doubtless why children often seem the most natural philosophers.)

    2. The pathos of distance, as it appears in Nietzsche's genealogical polemics, is clearly too complex a concept to address in brief notes. For me, however, Rilke's poetology of the 'infinite distances between people' (and the need to love such distances by becoming each other's spiritual guardians, in order to effect a 'wonderful living side by side [...] whole and before an immense sky') returns the problem of the estrangement of souls to the centre of poetic existence. As Freud famously affirmed, psychoanalysis' discovery of the unconscious means that we moderns are no longer masters in our own house. But what such intrapsychic insufficiency points to is the interpsychic imperative that we function as each other's supplements, mirrors, doppelgangers and antagonists. (It's very difficult to proofread one's own prose, perceive one's own flaws or interpret one's own dreams for one very good reason: not so much the danger of narcissism, but rather its impossibility.)

    3. There is no prima facie evidence for the dead not being receptive and/or responsive to the vibrations, fulminations and ruminations of the living as far as I'm aware - one only has to dip the briefest of toes into the enormously varied cross-cultural evidence for the transmigration of souls, poltergeist activity, hauntings, visitations and spirit communications down the ages. If life is indeed a special form of being dead, death must be an impersonal form of life, indeed both its wellspring and homecoming. Of course, life and death are participating in one another all the time in both directions. The material garb of being is undeniable, but hardly determinative. Von Trier's stupendous 'Breaking The Waves', in its depiction of Bess's posthumous manifestation to her mourners, is one magnificent cinematic testament to this permeability in our own time.

    4. It is doubly perplexing to me to see the dead (let alone the living) tethered to a politics of 'rights' (the 'right to reply' being an especially virulent pseudo-entitlement in the modern world) and/or 'consent' (fully informed consent to anything being only possible for angels, for whom life manifests as total radiance).

    5. As for Nietzsche's concept of eternal recurrence, its sources and intertexts - from the Ancient Egyptians and Indian philosophy to Heine, Vogt, Dostoevksy and Blanqui (conscious knowledge of which, for Nietzsche, is contested and contestable) - means, at least, there is no obvious need to privilege Nietzsche's own vision of a concept that one might as well call archetypal. In 'The Gay Science', where it most famously appears, it is perhaps worth pointing out that it is initially raised as a question whispered by a demon that in turn engenders a duality. First, it is fantasised as the 'greatest weight', a teeth-gnashing horror. But, if one were optimally disposed toward life, Nietzsche enjoins, nothing might be craved more fervently as life's 'divine confirmation and seal'. For the early Nietzsche of 'The Birth of Tragedy', such tragic affirmation (which he also links to his ethic of 'amor fati') could even function as a 'metaphysical comfort'. Hence, it seems clear, eternal recurrence engendered a sense of internal contestation within Nietzsche himself and, as such, cannot be extrapolated as a stabilised 'position' without doing violence to its genesis.

    ReplyDelete